I'm not dead yet

Fans of Monty Python and the Holy Grail may smile when they hear that familiar dull clank, accompanied by the plaintive cry: bring out your dead!

But not everybody is laughing, particularly those on the front lines of donation after cardiocirculatory death (DCD), a practice whereby medical teams remove organs for transplantation from individuals who have recently died.

Of course, this is all well and good – unless the donor is not quite dead.

In a recent article in Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities, the authors cite many troubling problems with DCD, including unreliable “consensus statements” supporting the practice, unjustifiable premortum procedures that do not benefit the donor, misleading assertions that DCD conforms to current medical procedure and to the law, and conflicts of interest in the DCD process itself. But the most disturbing of the paper’s assertions is that DCD donors may not, in fact, be dead at all.

In his evaluation of the article, F1000 Faculty Member Tom Woodcock writes,

The law’s Dead Donor Rule necessitates some gerrymandering of the definition of death in societies committed to lawful organ donation, and, while other contributors to this debate have called for the rule to be abandoned {1}, Joffe and colleagues take the strict Kantian position that the rule must be observed and veracity demanded of the transplant team, even if this results in fewer donations.

The dead donor rule, write the authors, “claims that humans must be dead before vital organs can be taken, and is intended to prevent the following: patients killed by organ retrieval, harm or exploitation of the weak/vulnerable, mistrust of doctors and transplantation, and treating a patient merely as a means to organs.”

Again, all well and good. However, it’s apparently harder to determine if someone is dead than one might guess.

Let’s consider a person who has given their informed consent to be a DCD donor. It all starts out innocently enough, when, having determined that the time has come, someone pulls the plug on our donor’s life support. If circulation stops within two hours, the individual can be a donor, after which the next two to ten minutes become a frenzy of ambiguity. That’s because death can be declared during this time period, although whether the transplant team uses the two- or the ten-minute rule, or something in between, varies from clinic to clinic. Similarly, the tools and procedures used to confirm death are not standardized between countries or even hospitals.

Then there is the problem of whether the person will stay dead. Irreversibility is one of the prerequisites of declaring death by absent circulation. That said, the authors take pains to distinguish “permanence” from “irreversibility.” Perhaps they capture the dilemma most vividly with this metaphor:

Is a drowning man dead because no one will swim out to save him? Or is he merely going to die?

And let’s not even talk about the Lazarus phenomenon, where previously dead patients come back to life – eerie.

The authors conclude,

…honesty requires that we face these problems instead of avoiding them. Until the concerns we describe are seriously considered, full public disclosure occurs, and fully informed consent is obtained from donors, there should be a moratorium on the practice of DCD.

In other words, don’t bring out your dead. Leave them in there for a while: we may need to rethink our policies.

In lively Socratic repartee, evaluator Tom Woodcock begs to disagree with a strict Kantian approach:

At the altar of the Categorical Imperative and the fully autonomous agent, Kant was also able to justify infanticide, duelling and lethal medical research on convicted criminals. In more modern times, the utilitarian philosopher Peter Singer of Monash and Princeton Universities has argued cogently for medical researchers to use demented humans in preference to sentient great apes {2}. Outlandish conclusions are not incompatible with academic philosophical discourse.

previous post

Cell traffic

next post

The role of the nucleus in disease

2 thoughts on “I'm not dead yet”

  1. Donation after cardiac death has now become an established second pathway for deceased donor organ donation in many countries. There are now published guidelines which underpin practice, the most recent of which comes from the United Kingdom, the NICE guideline-http://guidance.nice.org.uk/CG135 which is also now published in summary form -Donor identification and consent for deceased organ donation:summary of NICE guidance. British Medical Journal 2012;344:e341.

    Many patients are receiving via transplantation valuable organs from DCD donors, hence any call for a moratorium would have major consequences, and these consequences do not seem to be mentioned.

  2. D. John Doyle says:

    The lack of a sufficient organs from brain-dead donors has lead to the occasional use of non-heart-beating organ donors. Here, patients who are not brain-dead but do not have a “reasonable chance” of recovery are brought to the operating room where they are prepped for surgery, followed by the withdrawal of all life-support measures. Some time later their heart stops. A period of time later (typically 5 minutes after the final heart beat), surgeons rush in to retrieve organs [1].

    Some have criticized the definition of death used in non-heart-beating organ donation programs noting that asystole might not be permanent so long the heart might be restored by vigorous resuscitation efforts [2]. In addition, several non-heart-beating organ donation protocols allow ante-mortem interventions that are not intended to benefit the donor. For instance, high-dose heparin is sometimes given to prevent blood clotting. However, since the heparin is not administered for the benefit of the patient, some professionals argue that its administration is unethical [3].

    Another issue concerns timing. Doig and Rocker [4] explain the problem as follows:

    With the need to reduce warm ischemia, organs must be recovered as quickly as possible after the cessation of cardiac activity. The simple question becomes: when in the course of ascertaining death, is the patient dead, and when can organs be taken?

    Referring to a report from the Institutes of Medicine [5] they also note:

    The recent Institutes of Medicine report identified variability between centres in the duration of asystole required prior to organ retrieval (2–20 min), and that limited research has been conducted on the likelihood of spontaneous “auto-resuscitation.” Their report recommended adoption of five minutes of observed cardiac asystole, with a caveat that further research is required to confirm that auto-resuscitation does not occur during this interval. Meanwhile, some centres continue to use an interval of asystole as short as two minutes. Despite the premise of certainty in determining irreversible death, it is worrisome that centres can not agree to adopt a common standard.

    Clearly, the concept of organ donation after cardiac death will remain controversial for some time to come.

    REFERENCES

    [1] Bernat JL, D’Alessandro AM, Port FK, Bleck TP, Heard SO, Medina J, Rosenbaum SH, DeVita MA, Gaston RS, Merion RM, et al. Report of a National Conference on Donation after Cardiac Death. Am J Transplant. 2006;6:281–291.

    [2] Maleck WH, Piper SN, Triem J, Boldt J, Zittel FU. Unexpected return of spontaneous circulation after cessation of resuscitation (Lazarus phenomenon). Resuscitation. 1998;39:125–128.

    [3] Doig CJ, Rocker G. Retrieving organs from non-heart-beating organ donors: a review of medical and ethical issues. Can J Anesth 2003 50: 1069-1076.

    [4] Institute of Medicine. Non-Heart-Beating Organ Transplantation: Practices and Protocols. Washington DC: Institute of Medicine National Academy Press; 2000.

Legacy comments are closed.

User comments must be in English, comprehensible and relevant to the post under discussion. We reserve the right to remove any comments that we consider to be inappropriate, offensive or otherwise in breach of the User Comment Terms and Conditions. Commenters must not use a comment for personal attacks.

Click here to post comment and indicate that you accept the Commenting Terms and Conditions.